Monday, November 14, 2011

"Flesh Animated by Soul"


By William Keating, Regis 12

It can sometimes seem that the science of the brain overshadows the soul in the model of human consciousness. Yet Dr. Al Burke, Regis ’49 and Prof. of Religion and English at Hofstra University, contends that studying the brain alone is a limited pursuit, because neuroscientists are restricted to a “narrow epistemology,” i.e. inductive reasoning. In contrast, he argues, the scholars of the Humanities have a variety of epistemological tools at their disposal, including deductive reasoning. Dr. Burke says that it is this freedom and flexibility that allows a thorough and gratifying inquiry into our understanding of the human condition, including the nature of religious belief and the soul.

This introduced the topic of his lecture, the Platonic dialogue “The Phaedo.” But why that text?  In “The Phaedo,” Plato records the first attempt in the Western Tradition to postulate the theory of the “spiritual” soul, distinct in substance from the body. This concept separates the physical and spiritual into the body and soul, distinguishing between the mortal and immortal attributes of the human being.

Dr. Burke revealed that those ancient philosophers who believed in a spiritual soul, primarily Socrates and Plato, were among a minority, with the rest believing (as later Aristotle did) in a material soul or in no soul at all. These observations prefaced Dr. Burke’s presentation of Socrates as a radical thinker, a man who caused a paradigm shift in philosophy, away from cosmology (the study of the universe and the four elements: Earth Wind, Fire, and Water) and toward the study of ethics.

The central theme of Dr. Burke’s lecture was the philosophical disdain for the body raised in “The Phaedo,” that the body was in fact “the prison house of the soul.” Believing that the purpose of life is to seek truth, Socrates in “The Phaedo” describes the body as distracting from that purpose, constantly pursuing sustenance and reacting to emotions such as fear, desire, and affection. On the other hand, Socrates attributes to the soul the intellect and all that is like the divine, attempting to justify his belief that there is an immortal aspect of humanity. This tenet of Greek philosophy has impacted discussions of the soul for millennia, even to the present. This phenomenon can be attributed in part to Christianity, Dr. Burke explained, which was heavily influenced by Greek thought as it spread through the Mediterranean, and shared much in common with the Greek philosophy of the immortal soul.


“The Phaedo,” Dr. Burke divulged, is also important to the literature of the soul because it contains Socrates’ account of life after death, his “Orphic myth,” which suggests a parallel with the Judeo-Christian model of the spiritual world. Although the two developed independently, Dr. Burke explained that the afterlife described in “The Phaedo” is analogous to the Christian purgatory, heaven, and hell, in so far as Socrates adapts the traditional Greek view on Hades to include punishment for vices and the purification of the spirit.

Yet one must be careful not to approach the text with retroactive bias; as Dr. Burke pointed out, the Judeo-Christian model of the soul differs greatly from that of Plato, even as it articulates an identical justification of “eternal life.” Nevertheless, rather than insist on a division of body and spirit, scripture portrays their immortal union, as in a passage read by Dr. Burke: “The dead shall live again, their bodies shall rise” (Isaiah 26:19). In fact, the Bible treats the body with reverence, calling it the “temple of the Holy Spirit,” a far cry from the disdain for the corporeal form exhibited in “The Phaedo.”  This insight builds a more cooperative model of body and soul, based on the interpretation of Judeo-Christian message of spiritual and bodily unification.

Dr. Burke began his presentation of “The Phaedo” with a quote from Bishop John Robinson: “Man doesn’t have a body, he is a body. He is flesh animated by soul; the whole is a psycho-physical unity.” If we take anything from studying the history of the soul, let it be an understanding of how we arrived at the conception of spirituality we now have, let us learn the lessons afforded us by our perspective. It may be that the competition of epistemologies between the Sciences and the Humanities, neurology and philosophy, is as misguided as the conflict proposed by Plato between a divine soul and contemptible body. Perhaps these rivaling epistemologies differ less than we think; it may be true that they, like body and soul, are capable of increasing understanding more as a whole than as individual "ways of knowing" (i.e., epistemologies).

What advantage does this concept of unity offer in regard to our future study in the Seminar? While it can be difficult for us to distribute our concentration evenly among three models of consciousness, each offers us valuable insight into the human condition. It seems to me that the aim of this Seminar is attained in Dr. Burke’s response to “The Phaedo”—that the investigation of consciousness is best served by cooperation among the constructs of brain, mind, and soul, that more can be achieved in collaboration than in contradiction.

No comments:

Post a Comment